Pluralism and the Mind , livre ebook

icon

184

pages

icon

English

icon

Ebooks

2011

Écrit par

Publié par

icon jeton

Vous pourrez modifier la taille du texte de cet ouvrage

Lire un extrait
Lire un extrait

Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne En savoir plus

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris
icon

184

pages

icon

English

icon

Ebooks

2011

icon jeton

Vous pourrez modifier la taille du texte de cet ouvrage

Lire un extrait
Lire un extrait

Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne En savoir plus

Paul Feyerabend noted that '... the world which we want to explore is a largely unknown entity. We must, therefore, keep our options open and ... not restrict ourselves in advance.' (1975, p. 20). Given that consciousness is poorly understood and vaguely defined, such advice seems sound, but is frequently ignored in favour of an insistence that a scientific theory of consciousness must be reducible to current monist physics and biology.This book argues that such an insistence is historically unsupportable, theoretically incoherent and unnecessary. The author instead makes the case for emergent property pluralism. New concepts of emergent mental properties are needed in part because of the failure of mainstream approaches (like computationalism or dynamical systems) satisfactorily to address issues like subjective volition, autonomy and creativity. The author sees personal consciousness as active and classifiable as a subset of the wider problem of biological causation. ('Biological causation' is my term for issues like downwards causation, 'final causes,' purposive behaviour and autonomy that are poorly handled by conventional evolutionary, computational or dynamical systems models (See Rosen, 1991, Ho, 2008). Rosen's approach is especially useful from a pluralistic perspective because of his insistence that 'no one mode of causal entailment suffices to understand anything' (Rosen, 1991, p. 13.))The book is split into three sections. Part one builds an historical case for pluralism. Part two deconstructs insistent monism and mainstream models before addressing biological causation. Part three explores the consequences of such an alternative approach by examining specific phenomena like free will, the self and evolutionary emergence.
Voir icon arrow

Publié par

Date de parution

03 novembre 2011

Nombre de lectures

1

EAN13

9781845403287

Langue

English

Title Page
PLURALISM AND THE MIND
Consciousness, Worldviews and the Limits of Science
Matthew Colborn


imprint-academic.com



Publisher Information
Copyright © Matthew Colborn, 2011
The moral rights of the author have been asserted
No part of this publication may be reproduced in any form without permission, except for the quotation of brief passages in criticism and discussion.
Originally published in the UK by Imprint Academic
PO Box 200, Exeter EX5 5YX, UK
Originally published in the USA by Imprint Academic
Philosophy Documentation Center
PO Box 7147, Charlottesville, VA 22906-7147, USA
Digital version converted and published in 2011 by
Andrews UK Limited
www.andrewsuk.com



Dedication
FOR MY PARENTS



Acknowledgments
This book has many sources, but owes a significant part of its origin to the Master’s course in cognitive science at the University of Birmingham, attended in 1996–7, where I first grappled with the baffling mystery that is consciousness. Thanks to all my tutors there. The most recent inspiration was reviewing Edward and Emily Kelly’s Irreducible Mind for the European Journal of Parapsychology in 2009. This volume showed me that it was possible to formulate coherent alternatives to monistic physicalism, even though my views differ in some respects. Thanks also to the Society for Psychical Research for their support over the years.
I owe much to other’s scholarship, but especially that of M.R. Bennett, Walter Elsasser, Paul Feyerabend, P.M.S. Hacker, Mary Midgley, Karl Popper, Steven Rose, Robert Rosen, Raymond Tallis and B. Alan Wallace. People who have read portions of the manuscript and/or have been significantly influential in shaping the ideas expressed here include Henry Bauer, Susan Blackmore, Stephen Braude, Richard Broughton, Edward F. Kelly, Emily Williams Kelly, Alan Gauld, Elisabet Sahtouris, Rupert Sheldrake, Aaron Sloman, Paul Stevens and Charles Tart. Help and encouragement has been supplied at various times by Michael Brown, Rita Carter, Cal Cooper, William Edmondson, David Luke, Robert McLuhan, Sarah Proud, Serena Roney-Dougal, Adrian Ryan, Christine Simmonds and all the others who have accompanied me on this exploratory journey. Thanks especially to Paul and Charla Devereux for inviting me to attend a study day on consciousness in spring 2010, which got me over a serious case of writer’s block. Chapter five of this book owes a lot to that day. Thanks, too, go to Chris Roe and Simon Sherwood at the University of Northampton, who invited me to talk in the early stages of writing.
Thanks to my parents, who have supported me through some difficult times and especially my father, whose enthusiasm for this project has been one of the things that got me through to the end. Any mistakes, omissions or misinterpretations are my own. I have been as careful as possible with crediting sources, and any omissions will be corrected in future editions.



Introduction: The Persistent Question
The fundamental conceptions of psychology are practically very clear to us, but theoretically they are very confused, and one easily makes the obscurest assumptions in this science without realizing, until challenged, what internal difficulties they involve.
—William James, Principles of Psychology , 1890
Introduction
This is a book about the mind and its place in nature. It is an attempt to bridge the yawning gap between personal experiences of consciousness and the images of mind that frequently appear in the literature of the various cognitive sciences. There is also the need to understand better why such a gap exists in the first place, and whether it can—or should—ever be closed by a ‘definitive’ theory of consciousness that is satisfactory—or at least plausible—to all. But to begin, here are a few examples of subjective experience.
The Mystery of Consciousness
1. ‘The sky is pale blue today, with fluffy clouds. The sun is bright, and there is a slight bite in the air. A wind is blowing the late-summer leaves and the flowers on the patio out of my window are bright red. Every so often, a nearby workman operates an electric cutter that makes the hairs on the back of my neck stand up. It’s a relief when the motor stops, because you can hear the birds.’
2. ‘Yes because he never did a thing like that before as ask to get his breakfast in bed with a couple of eggs since the City Arms hotel when he used to be pretending to be laid up with a sick voice doing his highness to make himself interesting for that old faggot Mrs Riordan that he thought he had a great leg of and the never left us a farthing all for masses for herself and her soul greatest miser ever was …’ [1]
3. ‘About two years ago, while on holiday in Cornwall, I went for a walk with my sister along the beach … My sister walked on in front of me; I was left alone. It was as if time had stood still. I could think of nothing, I only felt I was “somewhere else.” I was part of something bigger and absolutely beyond me. My problems and my life didn’t matter at all because I was such a tiny part of a great whole.’ [2]
4. ‘… And there were always choices to make. Every day, every hour, offered the opportunity to make a decision, a decision which determined whether you would or would not submit to those powers which threatened to rob you of your very self, your inner freedom; which determined whether or not you would become a plaything of circumstance, renouncing freedom and dignity to become molded into the form of the typical inmate.’ [3]
5. ‘As the drug [an anaesthetic] began to work, I slipped down and lost awareness and feeling of my body. Visual impressions were relatively Spartan, but were mostly beige. Had experience of “white darkness” at one point, and complex patterns in dark brown against white beige very like the side-decorations in Tibetan art …
‘Reality felt gooey, or made of ice cream mixed with syrup. Feelings: at one point, I remember smiling and saying that I knew what the Buddhists were talking about. It was like I’d climbed a mountain to see a vast plain of “reality” and that it was good and light … These are metaphors; what I experienced, for fleeting moments, was ineffable.’
All five of the previous paragraphs describe different types of subjective experience. The first is a simple description of what lies outside my window. The second is a quotation from the novel Ulysses (1922) by James Joyce, which records the ramblings of the sleeping mind of Molly Bloom. The third is a description of a spontaneous mystical experience. The fourth is from Victor Frankl’s Man’s Search For Meaning , describing everyday life in Auschwitz, and the final one is an account of the extraordinary distortions of consciousness that occur when an hallucinogenic drug is administered. And these paragraphs are just pallid representations of the rich and various subjective experiences that are possible for a human being.
Scientists today are in many respects poorly equipped for the investigation of subjective experience, [4] and a cursory look at the literature reveals a mind that seems in some respects quite removed from the rich, organic and multifaceted experiences above. Compare 1–5 with the following quotes:
A. ‘It seems to me to make no sense (in scientific terms) to try to distinguish sharply between acts that result from conscious intention and those that result from our reflexes or are caused by disease or damage to the brain.’ [5]
B. ‘… the mind is fundamentally a sentient computing device, taking sentences as input from sensory transducers, performing logical operations on them, and issuing other sentences as output.’ [6]
C. ‘… the [Robotic system] CADBLIND Mark I certainly doesn’t have any qualia … So it does indeed follow from my comparison that I am claiming that we don’t have qualia [i.e. private, ineffable, subjective experiences] either. The sort of difference that people imagine there to be between any machine and a human experiencer … is one I am firmly denying: There is no such sort of difference. There just seems to be.’ [7]
D. ‘Big Ideas sometimes match the structure and function of the human brain such that the brain causes us to see the world in ways that make it virtually impossible not to believe them.’ [8]
E. ‘… there is nothing more [than brain function], no magic, no additional components to account for every thought, each perception and emotion, all our memories, our personality, fears, loves and curiosities.’ [9]
If we take passages 1–5 to be reasonably accurate descriptions of their respective experiences, then they challenge the claims in A–E. It is true that there are some points of correspondence. For example, one could imagine some version of passage 2, which consists of garbled thoughts, being spewed out by a computer or ‘sentient computing device’ (statement B); although it’s actually an expression of some complicated social intuitions, not to mention complaints.
But what about passage 4 and passage A? The writer of passage 4, a concentration camp inmate, describes constantly having to make internal decisions that could result in life or death. This seems completely at odds with the statement that there is essentially no difference between the behaviour caused by brain damage and that caused by a conscious decision.
Now compare passage B with passages 3 and 5, the mystical and drug-induced experiences respectively. Could a ‘sentient computing device’, or even a robot, possibly have such experiences? Maybe, maybe not—it really depends upon the ultimate nature of such experiences, which remain obscure (and dubbing them hallucinations begs the question of the hallucination’s nature). But at first sight, such experiences don

Voir icon more
Alternate Text